Proof lengths for instances of the Paris-Harrington principle (Q526964): Difference between revisions
From MaRDI portal
Created a new Item |
Created claim: DBLP publication ID (P1635): journals/apal/Freund17, #quickstatements; #temporary_batch_1731547958265 |
||
(7 intermediate revisions by 6 users not shown) | |||
Property / review text | |||
It is well known that Peano arthmetic cannot prove the Paris-Harrington principle \(\forall k\), \(m\), \(n\exists N\mathrm{PH}(k,m,n,N)\), where \(\mathrm{PH}(k,m,n,N)\) means that any \(k\)-colouring of \([N]^m\) has a large homogeneous set of size at least \(m\). However, the instances \(\exists N\,\mathrm{PH}(\overline k,\overline m,\overline n,N)\) of the principle are provable already in Robinson's arithmetic \(Q\), being true \(\Sigma_1\) sentences. The principal problem investigated in this paper is how long the proofs of these instances need to be in PA and its fragments, in terms of the parameters \(k\), \(m\), \(n\). Notice that on the one hand, the instances have proofs of length \(O(\log(k+m+n))\) in theories that prove the full Paris-Harrington principle; on the other hand, there is no obvious way how to prove them in \(Q\) other than by exhibiting the witness \(N\), which is astronomically large (its growth is related to the \(F_{\varepsilon_0}\) function in the fast-growing hierarchy). In fact, as stated by the author, the intent is rather to study what fragments of PA have natural proofs of the instances \(\exists N\,\mathrm{PH}(\overline k,\overline m,\overline n,N)\). While this is a vague informal question, one can argue that for lower bounds astronomically large proofs are not natural. (For upper bounds, we may hope just to recognize a natural proof when we see it.) As shown in [\textit{P. Hájek} and \textit{P. Pudlák}, Metamathematics of first-order arithmetic. Berlin: Springer-Verlag (1993; Zbl 0781.03047)], even the partly universally quantified instances \(\forall m\,\exists N\,\mathrm{PH}(\overline k,m,\overline n,N)\) have (fairly natural) primitive recursive \(I\Sigma_{n-1}\)-proofs. The present paper complements this by showing that \(I\Sigma_{n-2}\)-proofs of \(\exists N\,\mathrm{PH}(\overline{e(n)},\overline{n+1},\overline n,N)\), where \(e(n)=10^{35(n-2)^2}\), are absurdly large (of size at least \(F_{\varepsilon_0}(n-3)\) for \(n\gg 0\)), and similarly for \(I\Sigma_{n-3}\)-proofs of \(\exists N\,\mathrm{PH}(\overline8,\overline{n+1},\overline n,N)\) where the number of colours is constant. The basic tool used in the paper is the observation that if a theory \(T\) proves the uniform \(\Sigma_1\)-reflection principle for a proof predicate \(P\), then \(P\)-proofs of instances of a \(\Sigma_1\) formula cannot be much shorter than witnesses of the formula, up to speed-up given by a \(T\)-provably total recursive function. Notice that this applies to a proof predicate of a fixed theory, whereas in the main result of the paper, the theory (\(I\Sigma_{n-2}\)) varies with \(n\). In order to achieve this dependency, the author takes for \(P\) a slow provability predicate for PA, as in [\textit{S.-D.Friedman} et al., Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 164, No. 3, 382--393 (2013; Zbl 1263.03055)]. The technical part of the paper is an analysis of provably total recursive functions of the theory PA + the \(\Sigma_1\)-reflection principle for slow provability in PA. | |||
Property / review text: It is well known that Peano arthmetic cannot prove the Paris-Harrington principle \(\forall k\), \(m\), \(n\exists N\mathrm{PH}(k,m,n,N)\), where \(\mathrm{PH}(k,m,n,N)\) means that any \(k\)-colouring of \([N]^m\) has a large homogeneous set of size at least \(m\). However, the instances \(\exists N\,\mathrm{PH}(\overline k,\overline m,\overline n,N)\) of the principle are provable already in Robinson's arithmetic \(Q\), being true \(\Sigma_1\) sentences. The principal problem investigated in this paper is how long the proofs of these instances need to be in PA and its fragments, in terms of the parameters \(k\), \(m\), \(n\). Notice that on the one hand, the instances have proofs of length \(O(\log(k+m+n))\) in theories that prove the full Paris-Harrington principle; on the other hand, there is no obvious way how to prove them in \(Q\) other than by exhibiting the witness \(N\), which is astronomically large (its growth is related to the \(F_{\varepsilon_0}\) function in the fast-growing hierarchy). In fact, as stated by the author, the intent is rather to study what fragments of PA have natural proofs of the instances \(\exists N\,\mathrm{PH}(\overline k,\overline m,\overline n,N)\). While this is a vague informal question, one can argue that for lower bounds astronomically large proofs are not natural. (For upper bounds, we may hope just to recognize a natural proof when we see it.) As shown in [\textit{P. Hájek} and \textit{P. Pudlák}, Metamathematics of first-order arithmetic. Berlin: Springer-Verlag (1993; Zbl 0781.03047)], even the partly universally quantified instances \(\forall m\,\exists N\,\mathrm{PH}(\overline k,m,\overline n,N)\) have (fairly natural) primitive recursive \(I\Sigma_{n-1}\)-proofs. The present paper complements this by showing that \(I\Sigma_{n-2}\)-proofs of \(\exists N\,\mathrm{PH}(\overline{e(n)},\overline{n+1},\overline n,N)\), where \(e(n)=10^{35(n-2)^2}\), are absurdly large (of size at least \(F_{\varepsilon_0}(n-3)\) for \(n\gg 0\)), and similarly for \(I\Sigma_{n-3}\)-proofs of \(\exists N\,\mathrm{PH}(\overline8,\overline{n+1},\overline n,N)\) where the number of colours is constant. The basic tool used in the paper is the observation that if a theory \(T\) proves the uniform \(\Sigma_1\)-reflection principle for a proof predicate \(P\), then \(P\)-proofs of instances of a \(\Sigma_1\) formula cannot be much shorter than witnesses of the formula, up to speed-up given by a \(T\)-provably total recursive function. Notice that this applies to a proof predicate of a fixed theory, whereas in the main result of the paper, the theory (\(I\Sigma_{n-2}\)) varies with \(n\). In order to achieve this dependency, the author takes for \(P\) a slow provability predicate for PA, as in [\textit{S.-D.Friedman} et al., Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 164, No. 3, 382--393 (2013; Zbl 1263.03055)]. The technical part of the paper is an analysis of provably total recursive functions of the theory PA + the \(\Sigma_1\)-reflection principle for slow provability in PA. / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / reviewed by | |||
Property / reviewed by: Emil Jeřábek / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / Mathematics Subject Classification ID | |||
Property / Mathematics Subject Classification ID: 03F30 / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / Mathematics Subject Classification ID | |||
Property / Mathematics Subject Classification ID: 03F20 / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / Mathematics Subject Classification ID | |||
Property / Mathematics Subject Classification ID: 03D20 / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / Mathematics Subject Classification ID | |||
Property / Mathematics Subject Classification ID: 03F40 / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / zbMATH DE Number | |||
Property / zbMATH DE Number: 6715656 / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / zbMATH Keywords | |||
Peano arithmetic | |||
Property / zbMATH Keywords: Peano arithmetic / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / zbMATH Keywords | |||
proof length | |||
Property / zbMATH Keywords: proof length / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / zbMATH Keywords | |||
Paris-Harrington principle | |||
Property / zbMATH Keywords: Paris-Harrington principle / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / zbMATH Keywords | |||
finite Ramsey theorem | |||
Property / zbMATH Keywords: finite Ramsey theorem / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / zbMATH Keywords | |||
slow consistency | |||
Property / zbMATH Keywords: slow consistency / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / zbMATH Keywords | |||
fast growing hierarchy | |||
Property / zbMATH Keywords: fast growing hierarchy / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / MaRDI profile type | |||
Property / MaRDI profile type: MaRDI publication profile / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / OpenAlex ID | |||
Property / OpenAlex ID: W2253714458 / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / Wikidata QID | |||
Property / Wikidata QID: Q57948752 / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / arXiv ID | |||
Property / arXiv ID: 1601.08185 / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: Proof-theoretic analysis by iterated reflection / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: Notation systems for infinitary derivations / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: Q3773880 / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: Q4215632 / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: Slow consistency / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: Q5286672 / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: Q3140637 / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: Rapidly growing Ramsey functions / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: On the number of steps in proofs / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: On the interpretation of non-finitist proofs–Part II / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: Streamlined subrecursive degree theory / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: An Unprovable Ramsey-Type Theorem / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: Q3893931 / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: Eine Klassifikation der ε<sub>0</sub>‐Rekursiven Funktionen / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: The Ackermann functions are not optimal, but by how much? / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: Harvey Friedman's research on the foundations of mathematics / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: Transfinite induction within Peano arithmetic / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / cites work | |||
Property / cites work: A classification of the ordinal recursive functions / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
Property / DBLP publication ID | |||
Property / DBLP publication ID: journals/apal/Freund17 / rank | |||
Normal rank | |||
links / mardi / name | links / mardi / name | ||
Latest revision as of 02:37, 14 November 2024
scientific article
Language | Label | Description | Also known as |
---|---|---|---|
English | Proof lengths for instances of the Paris-Harrington principle |
scientific article |
Statements
Proof lengths for instances of the Paris-Harrington principle (English)
0 references
15 May 2017
0 references
It is well known that Peano arthmetic cannot prove the Paris-Harrington principle \(\forall k\), \(m\), \(n\exists N\mathrm{PH}(k,m,n,N)\), where \(\mathrm{PH}(k,m,n,N)\) means that any \(k\)-colouring of \([N]^m\) has a large homogeneous set of size at least \(m\). However, the instances \(\exists N\,\mathrm{PH}(\overline k,\overline m,\overline n,N)\) of the principle are provable already in Robinson's arithmetic \(Q\), being true \(\Sigma_1\) sentences. The principal problem investigated in this paper is how long the proofs of these instances need to be in PA and its fragments, in terms of the parameters \(k\), \(m\), \(n\). Notice that on the one hand, the instances have proofs of length \(O(\log(k+m+n))\) in theories that prove the full Paris-Harrington principle; on the other hand, there is no obvious way how to prove them in \(Q\) other than by exhibiting the witness \(N\), which is astronomically large (its growth is related to the \(F_{\varepsilon_0}\) function in the fast-growing hierarchy). In fact, as stated by the author, the intent is rather to study what fragments of PA have natural proofs of the instances \(\exists N\,\mathrm{PH}(\overline k,\overline m,\overline n,N)\). While this is a vague informal question, one can argue that for lower bounds astronomically large proofs are not natural. (For upper bounds, we may hope just to recognize a natural proof when we see it.) As shown in [\textit{P. Hájek} and \textit{P. Pudlák}, Metamathematics of first-order arithmetic. Berlin: Springer-Verlag (1993; Zbl 0781.03047)], even the partly universally quantified instances \(\forall m\,\exists N\,\mathrm{PH}(\overline k,m,\overline n,N)\) have (fairly natural) primitive recursive \(I\Sigma_{n-1}\)-proofs. The present paper complements this by showing that \(I\Sigma_{n-2}\)-proofs of \(\exists N\,\mathrm{PH}(\overline{e(n)},\overline{n+1},\overline n,N)\), where \(e(n)=10^{35(n-2)^2}\), are absurdly large (of size at least \(F_{\varepsilon_0}(n-3)\) for \(n\gg 0\)), and similarly for \(I\Sigma_{n-3}\)-proofs of \(\exists N\,\mathrm{PH}(\overline8,\overline{n+1},\overline n,N)\) where the number of colours is constant. The basic tool used in the paper is the observation that if a theory \(T\) proves the uniform \(\Sigma_1\)-reflection principle for a proof predicate \(P\), then \(P\)-proofs of instances of a \(\Sigma_1\) formula cannot be much shorter than witnesses of the formula, up to speed-up given by a \(T\)-provably total recursive function. Notice that this applies to a proof predicate of a fixed theory, whereas in the main result of the paper, the theory (\(I\Sigma_{n-2}\)) varies with \(n\). In order to achieve this dependency, the author takes for \(P\) a slow provability predicate for PA, as in [\textit{S.-D.Friedman} et al., Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 164, No. 3, 382--393 (2013; Zbl 1263.03055)]. The technical part of the paper is an analysis of provably total recursive functions of the theory PA + the \(\Sigma_1\)-reflection principle for slow provability in PA.
0 references
Peano arithmetic
0 references
proof length
0 references
Paris-Harrington principle
0 references
finite Ramsey theorem
0 references
slow consistency
0 references
fast growing hierarchy
0 references