Nonconvergence in the theory of random orders (Q1177706): Difference between revisions

From MaRDI portal
RedirectionBot (talk | contribs)
Changed an Item
ReferenceBot (talk | contribs)
Changed an Item
 
(One intermediate revision by one other user not shown)
Property / MaRDI profile type
 
Property / MaRDI profile type: MaRDI publication profile / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q4035309 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Random orders / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: A counterexample in the theory of random orders / rank
 
Normal rank

Latest revision as of 10:34, 15 May 2024

scientific article
Language Label Description Also known as
English
Nonconvergence in the theory of random orders
scientific article

    Statements

    Nonconvergence in the theory of random orders (English)
    0 references
    0 references
    26 June 1992
    0 references
    Let \(P_ k\) be the random poset of dimension \(k\) on \(n\) elements obtained by intersecting \(k\) randomly and independently chosen linear orders; for \(k=2\) this amounts to selecting a randon non-identity permutation in \(S_ n\), the symmetric group. Let \(P_ 2(n)=\hbox{Ran}(n)\). If \(A\) is a property of posets, one might consider expressions \(\lim_{n\to \infty}\hbox{Pr}[\hbox{Ran}(n)\vdash A]\), where the value 1 denotes almost always (aa) and the value 0 denotes almost never (an). Winkler and Brightwell have shown that such limits may take values other than 0 and 1 if the property \(A\) can be written as a first- order sentence and in this paper the author constructs a suitably clever complicated first-order sentence such that \(\lim_{n\to \infty}\text{Pr}[\hbox{Ran}(n)\vdash A]\) does not exist. The method employed has as intermediate product an important non-separability result based on a special universal representation lemma developed in the paper as well as the Trakhtenbrot-Vaught Theorem, viz., there is no separation procedure on first-order sentences \(A\) that returns `yes' when \(A\) holds aa and `no' when A holds an. The technique used involves the sentence \(A\), built up out of various component parts designed to fail in some critical way along with estimates of various functions \(\varphi (n)\) of \(n\) with the property that \(\lim_{n\to \infty}\varphi(n)=0\) and Pr\([\hbox{something troublesome happens}]\leq \varphi(n)\), permitting the avoiding of unwanted complications in the long run.
    0 references
    convergence
    0 references
    limit probability of first-order sentences
    0 references
    random poset
    0 references
    dimension
    0 references
    non-separability
    0 references
    0 references

    Identifiers

    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references