Subcountability under realizability (Q1098849): Difference between revisions

From MaRDI portal
Added link to MaRDI item.
Import241208061232 (talk | contribs)
Normalize DOI.
 
(2 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown)
Property / DOI
 
Property / DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093636613 / rank
Normal rank
 
Property / MaRDI profile type
 
Property / MaRDI profile type: MaRDI publication profile / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / full work available at URL
 
Property / full work available at URL: https://doi.org/10.1305/ndjfl/1093636613 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / OpenAlex ID
 
Property / OpenAlex ID: W2025502180 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / DOI
 
Property / DOI: 10.1305/NDJFL/1093636613 / rank
 
Normal rank

Latest revision as of 15:24, 10 December 2024

scientific article
Language Label Description Also known as
English
Subcountability under realizability
scientific article

    Statements

    Subcountability under realizability (English)
    0 references
    0 references
    1986
    0 references
    In constructive mathematics, a set a is discrete if it satisfies \(x,y\in a\to x=y\vee x\neq y.\) A set is countable if it is the range of a function on the integers, and subcountable if it is a subset of a countable set. Unlike in classical mathematics, subcountable sets need not be countable; even Baire space might be subcountable (e.g. if Church's thesis CT is true). All known discrete sets are subcountable, and if CT holds so are separable metric spaces. So the problem was raised whether it is consistent to assume (SCDS) all discrete sets are subcountable, or perhaps even the stronger (SCMS) all metric spaces are subcountable. (It is stronger because a discrete set can be given the discrete metric.) The paper shows the consistency of both these principles with intuitionistic ZF set theory IZF. The method is straightforward: the principles turn out to be recursively realized. The proof itself is not quite straightforward, requiring a clever ``reflection'' in which the realizer of \(x,y\in a\to x=y\vee x\neq y\) is shown to contain an object realized to be a ``subcounting function'' of a. (Lemma 2).
    0 references
    subcountable sets
    0 references
    Church's thesis
    0 references
    discrete sets
    0 references
    metric spaces
    0 references
    intuitionistic ZF set theory
    0 references

    Identifiers

    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references