Deciding unifiability and computing local unifiers in the description logic \(\mathcal{EL}\) without top constructor (Q2374390): Difference between revisions

From MaRDI portal
Importer (talk | contribs)
Created a new Item
 
ReferenceBot (talk | contribs)
Changed an Item
 
(3 intermediate revisions by 3 users not shown)
Property / MaRDI profile type
 
Property / MaRDI profile type: MaRDI publication profile / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / OpenAlex ID
 
Property / OpenAlex ID: W2477403571 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Deciding unifiability and computing local unifiers in the description logic \(\mathcal{EL}\) without top constructor / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Unification in the Description Logic $\mathcal{EL}$ without the Top Concept / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: SAT Encoding of Unification in $\mathcal{ELH}_{{R}^+}$ w.r.t. Cycle-Restricted Ontologies / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q4406531 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Unification in modal and description logics / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Unification in the Description Logic $\mathcal{EL}$ / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: SAT Encoding of Unification in $\mathcal{EL}$ / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Unification in the Description Logic EL / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Unification of concept terms in description logics / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q2751360 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: State-complexity of finite-state devices, state compressibility and incompressibility / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q3408862 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Alternation / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: A note on two problems in connexion with graphs / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q4198056 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Practical reasoning for very expressive description logics / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: A note on the space complexity of some decision problems for finite automata / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Solving SAT and SAT Modulo Theories / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Relationships between nondeterministic and deterministic tape complexities / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q4012244 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q3085175 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Undecidability of the unification and admissibility problems for modal and description logics / rank
 
Normal rank
links / mardi / namelinks / mardi / name
 

Latest revision as of 02:59, 13 July 2024

scientific article
Language Label Description Also known as
English
Deciding unifiability and computing local unifiers in the description logic \(\mathcal{EL}\) without top constructor
scientific article

    Statements

    Deciding unifiability and computing local unifiers in the description logic \(\mathcal{EL}\) without top constructor (English)
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    15 December 2016
    0 references
    \(\mathcal{EL}\) is the description logic built over two disjoint sets \(N_C\) and \(N_R\) of concept and role names, respectively, whose concept terms are of the form \(\top\) (the top concept), or \(c\) for \(c\in N_C\), or \(C\sqcap D\) with \(C\) and \(D\) concept terms, or \(\exists r.C\) for \(r\in N_R\) with \(C\) a concept term. The description logic \(\mathcal{EL}^{-\top}\) is the same except that \(\top\) is not a concept term. For instance, the concept of persons having a son, a daughter and a job can be expressed in \(\mathcal{EL}\) as \[ \mathrm{Person}\sqcap\exists\mathrm{child}.\mathrm{Male}\sqcap\exists\mathrm{child}.\mathrm{Female}\sqcap\exists\mathrm{job}.\top, \] whereas the concept of female professors can be expressed in \(\mathcal{EL}^{-\top}\) as either \[ \mathrm{Person}\sqcap\mathrm{Female}\sqcap\exists\mathrm{job}.\mathrm{Professor} \] or \[ \mathrm{Woman}\sqcap\exists\mathrm{job}.\mathrm{Teacher}\sqcap\mathrm{Researcher}, \] by substituting \(\mathrm{Teacher}\sqcap\mathrm{Researcher}\) for \(\mathrm{Professor}\) and \(\mathrm{Person}\sqcap\mathrm{Female}\) for \(\mathrm{Woman}\). This is an instance of \textit{unification}, where two concept terms are made equivalent by letting some concept names, treated as variables, be replaced by concept terms. In [\textit{F. Baader} and \textit{B. Morawska}, Lect. Notes Comput. Sci. 5595, 350--364 (2009; Zbl 1242.68300)], it was shown that deciding whether two concept terms in \(\mathcal{EL}\) are unifiable is NP-complete. Motivated by the existence of SNOMED CT, a large medical ontology all of whose concepts are expressed in \(\mathcal{EL}^{-\top}\), the authors show that, surprisingly, deciding whether two concept terms in \(\mathcal{EL}^\top\) are unifiable, is harder, namely \textsc{PSpace}-complete. The proof makes use of \textit{alternating finite automata}, that can make two kinds of transitions: nondeterministic transitions that ``guess'' the next state of the automaton, and ``universal'' transitions that force the automaton to explore every possible successor state. The authors also observe that unification in \(\mathcal{EL}^{-\top}\) {\parindent=0.6cm\begin{itemize}\item[{\(\bullet\)}] is equivalent to unification modulo the equational theory \(\mathrm{SLmO}\) of \textit{semilattices with monotone operators}, defined by the identities (1) \(x\wedge(y\wedge z)=(x\wedge y)\wedge z\), (2) \(x\wedge y=y\wedge x\), (3) \(x\wedge x=x\), and (4) \(f_i(x\wedge y)\wedge f_i(y)=f_i(x\wedge y)\) -- for instance, the concept term \(A\sqcap\exists r_3.(X\sqcap B)\) is put into correspondence with the equation \(a\wedge f_3(x\wedge b)\); \item[{\(\bullet\)}] can be used to decide unification in the fragment of the modal logic \(\mathrm{K}_m\) that is restricted to the connectives \(\wedge\) and \(\lozenge_{r_i}\), by making concept names correspond to propositional variables, \(\sqcap\) to \(\wedge\), and \(\exists r_i\) to \(\lozenge_i\). \end{itemize}}
    0 references
    0 references
    unification
    0 references
    description logics
    0 references

    Identifiers

    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references