Leibniz's logic and the ``cube of opposition'' (Q346757): Difference between revisions

From MaRDI portal
Importer (talk | contribs)
Created a new Item
 
Normalize DOI.
 
(6 intermediate revisions by 6 users not shown)
Property / DOI
 
Property / DOI: 10.1007/s11787-016-0143-2 / rank
Normal rank
 
Property / review text
 
The author relates Leibniz's logic, reconstructed as intensional algebra of concepts, to the traditional syllogistic theory of judgements as represented in the square of opposition. After reconsidering the traditional square and the corresponding theory, the author reconstructs Leibniz's intensional algebra as it can be found mainly in Leibniz's \textit{Generales inquisitiones} of 1686. One example for the differences is Leibniz's expression of the universal affirmative proposition ``Every S is P'' simply by ``S is P'' or ``S contains P''. Leibniz furthermore introduces a new operator of conceptual conjunction and proposes the unrestricted use of conceptual negation. The author reconstructs Leibniz's language \(L_1\), i.e., an extensional interpretation of the algebra of concepts. He arrives at a slightly modified form of the square of opposition in two variations (pp.\ 180--181). The author extensively discusses the validity of subalternation in \(L_1\) arriving at the conclusion ``Within the framework of Leibniz's `intensional' logic where the extension of a concept is interpreted as a set of \textit{possible} objects, the law of subalternation is valid, provided that this law -- or the entire square of opposition -- is \textit{restricted to self-consistent concepts}!'' (p.\ 183). In the next section, the author considers the quantification of the predicate as proposed by Leibniz in a fragment \textit{Mathesis rationis} of around 1700. The author can show that Leibniz's suggestions in respect to categorical forms are compatible with the standard square of predicate logic in the Fregean interpretation. But Leibniz also discusses four unorthodox propositions such as ``Every A is every B''. The author shows that these unorthodox propositions can be represented by an alternative square which can be intertwined with the former one to a cube of propositions. The author closes with a discussion of the meaning of Leibniz's unorthodox propositions.
Property / review text: The author relates Leibniz's logic, reconstructed as intensional algebra of concepts, to the traditional syllogistic theory of judgements as represented in the square of opposition. After reconsidering the traditional square and the corresponding theory, the author reconstructs Leibniz's intensional algebra as it can be found mainly in Leibniz's \textit{Generales inquisitiones} of 1686. One example for the differences is Leibniz's expression of the universal affirmative proposition ``Every S is P'' simply by ``S is P'' or ``S contains P''. Leibniz furthermore introduces a new operator of conceptual conjunction and proposes the unrestricted use of conceptual negation. The author reconstructs Leibniz's language \(L_1\), i.e., an extensional interpretation of the algebra of concepts. He arrives at a slightly modified form of the square of opposition in two variations (pp.\ 180--181). The author extensively discusses the validity of subalternation in \(L_1\) arriving at the conclusion ``Within the framework of Leibniz's `intensional' logic where the extension of a concept is interpreted as a set of \textit{possible} objects, the law of subalternation is valid, provided that this law -- or the entire square of opposition -- is \textit{restricted to self-consistent concepts}!'' (p.\ 183). In the next section, the author considers the quantification of the predicate as proposed by Leibniz in a fragment \textit{Mathesis rationis} of around 1700. The author can show that Leibniz's suggestions in respect to categorical forms are compatible with the standard square of predicate logic in the Fregean interpretation. But Leibniz also discusses four unorthodox propositions such as ``Every A is every B''. The author shows that these unorthodox propositions can be represented by an alternative square which can be intertwined with the former one to a cube of propositions. The author closes with a discussion of the meaning of Leibniz's unorthodox propositions. / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / reviewed by
 
Property / reviewed by: Volker Peckhaus / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / Mathematics Subject Classification ID
 
Property / Mathematics Subject Classification ID: 03A05 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / Mathematics Subject Classification ID
 
Property / Mathematics Subject Classification ID: 01A45 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / Mathematics Subject Classification ID
 
Property / Mathematics Subject Classification ID: 03-03 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / Mathematics Subject Classification ID
 
Property / Mathematics Subject Classification ID: 03B20 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / zbMATH DE Number
 
Property / zbMATH DE Number: 6657597 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / zbMATH Keywords
 
square of opposition
Property / zbMATH Keywords: square of opposition / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / zbMATH Keywords
 
theory of the syllogism
Property / zbMATH Keywords: theory of the syllogism / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / zbMATH Keywords
 
concept logic
Property / zbMATH Keywords: concept logic / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / zbMATH Keywords
 
Leibniz
Property / zbMATH Keywords: Leibniz / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / zbMATH Keywords
 
quantification of the predicate
Property / zbMATH Keywords: quantification of the predicate / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / zbMATH Keywords
 
individual concepts
Property / zbMATH Keywords: individual concepts / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / zbMATH Keywords
 
intensional algebra
Property / zbMATH Keywords: intensional algebra / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / MaRDI profile type
 
Property / MaRDI profile type: MaRDI publication profile / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / full work available at URL
 
Property / full work available at URL: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11787-016-0143-2 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / OpenAlex ID
 
Property / OpenAlex ID: W2321236795 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q3342501 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Leibniz on Intension and Extension / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q3918093 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q5817389 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q3924155 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / DOI
 
Property / DOI: 10.1007/S11787-016-0143-2 / rank
 
Normal rank
links / mardi / namelinks / mardi / name
 

Latest revision as of 15:02, 9 December 2024

scientific article
Language Label Description Also known as
English
Leibniz's logic and the ``cube of opposition''
scientific article

    Statements

    Leibniz's logic and the ``cube of opposition'' (English)
    0 references
    0 references
    30 November 2016
    0 references
    The author relates Leibniz's logic, reconstructed as intensional algebra of concepts, to the traditional syllogistic theory of judgements as represented in the square of opposition. After reconsidering the traditional square and the corresponding theory, the author reconstructs Leibniz's intensional algebra as it can be found mainly in Leibniz's \textit{Generales inquisitiones} of 1686. One example for the differences is Leibniz's expression of the universal affirmative proposition ``Every S is P'' simply by ``S is P'' or ``S contains P''. Leibniz furthermore introduces a new operator of conceptual conjunction and proposes the unrestricted use of conceptual negation. The author reconstructs Leibniz's language \(L_1\), i.e., an extensional interpretation of the algebra of concepts. He arrives at a slightly modified form of the square of opposition in two variations (pp.\ 180--181). The author extensively discusses the validity of subalternation in \(L_1\) arriving at the conclusion ``Within the framework of Leibniz's `intensional' logic where the extension of a concept is interpreted as a set of \textit{possible} objects, the law of subalternation is valid, provided that this law -- or the entire square of opposition -- is \textit{restricted to self-consistent concepts}!'' (p.\ 183). In the next section, the author considers the quantification of the predicate as proposed by Leibniz in a fragment \textit{Mathesis rationis} of around 1700. The author can show that Leibniz's suggestions in respect to categorical forms are compatible with the standard square of predicate logic in the Fregean interpretation. But Leibniz also discusses four unorthodox propositions such as ``Every A is every B''. The author shows that these unorthodox propositions can be represented by an alternative square which can be intertwined with the former one to a cube of propositions. The author closes with a discussion of the meaning of Leibniz's unorthodox propositions.
    0 references
    square of opposition
    0 references
    theory of the syllogism
    0 references
    concept logic
    0 references
    Leibniz
    0 references
    quantification of the predicate
    0 references
    individual concepts
    0 references
    intensional algebra
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references

    Identifiers

    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references