Uniform van Lambalgen's theorem fails for computable randomness (Q2304533): Difference between revisions

From MaRDI portal
RedirectionBot (talk | contribs)
Removed claim: reviewed by (P1447): Item:Q592003
RedirectionBot (talk | contribs)
Changed an Item
Property / reviewed by
 
Property / reviewed by: Vladik Ya. Kreinovich / rank
 
Normal rank

Revision as of 22:57, 19 February 2024

scientific article
Language Label Description Also known as
English
Uniform van Lambalgen's theorem fails for computable randomness
scientific article

    Statements

    Uniform van Lambalgen's theorem fails for computable randomness (English)
    0 references
    0 references
    12 March 2020
    0 references
    It is not possible to have a successful strategy in a game of chance. However, formalizing this statement is not easy, even for simple situations when the outcome of a game is determined by a (potentially infinite) sequence \(a_1a_2\ldots a_n\ldots\) of truly random bits: head or tail, red or black, etc. The usual formalization takes into account that the gambler starts with some amount of money. The gambler can stop after each \(n\); in this case, he/she will have the amount of money \(f(a_1\ldots a_n)\). Instead of taking this amount, the gambler can ask for one more cycle, with values \(f(a_1\ldots a_n0)\ge 0\) and \(f(a_1\ldots a_n1)\ge 0\) whose mathematical expectation \((f(a_1\ldots a_n0)+ f(a_1\ldots a_n1))/2\) is equal to the current amount. The resulting function \(f(a)\) from finite binary sequences to non-negative real numbers is known as a \textit{martingale}. For each gambling strategy (i.e., for each computable martingale \(f(a)\)), if a sequence \(\{a_i\}\) is truly random, then, while the gambler may earn some money, we do not expect the gambler with finite initial funds to be earning an unlimited amount of money -- so all the amounts \(f(a_1\ldots a_n)\) should be bounded. This idea underlies one of the natural definitions of randomness: an infinite sequence \(a_1a_2\ldots\) is \textit{computably random} if for each computable martingale \(f(a)\), the set of all the values \(f(a_1\ldots a_n)\) is bounded. This paper provides an unexpected counter-intuitive example of a sequence in which odd bits are computably random, even bits are computably random relative to the odd bits, but the whole sequence is not computably random: it has a martingale allowing infinitely increasing wins! Such examples are impossible if we use other definitions of randomness; so maybe computable randomness does not fully capture our intuitive idea of randomness? From the technical viewpoint, this paper's example is very subtle -- e.g., if we also require that odd bits are computably random relative to even bits, then the whole sequence is always computably random.
    0 references
    algorithmic randomness
    0 references
    martingale
    0 references
    computable randomness
    0 references
    van Lambalgen's theorem
    0 references

    Identifiers