Complete existentially closed locally finite groups (Q1057365): Difference between revisions

From MaRDI portal
Import240304020342 (talk | contribs)
Set profile property.
ReferenceBot (talk | contribs)
Changed an Item
 
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Some Constructions for Locally Finite Groups / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Complete Universal Locally Finite Groups / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q5729345 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q5675882 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Model theory for infinitary logic. Logic with countable conjunctions and finite quantifiers / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q4189277 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Existentially closed structures and Jensen's principle \(\diamond\) / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Uncountable universal locally finite groups / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Existenziell abgeschlossene lokal endliche p-Gruppen / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Embedding Theorems for Groups / rank
 
Normal rank

Latest revision as of 16:30, 14 June 2024

scientific article
Language Label Description Also known as
English
Complete existentially closed locally finite groups
scientific article

    Statements

    Complete existentially closed locally finite groups (English)
    0 references
    0 references
    1985
    0 references
    A group G is existentially closed (e.c.) in a class \({\mathfrak X}\) of groups, if \(G\in {\mathfrak X}\), and each finite system of equations and inequations, with coefficients in G, having a solution in some \({\mathfrak X}\)-group containing G, already has a solution in G. It turns out that when \({\mathfrak X}\) is the class of locally finite groups, one obtains in this way the universal locally finite groups, which are usually defined somewhat differently. This paper deals with groups that are e.c. in \({\mathfrak X}\), where \({\mathfrak X}\) is either the class of all locally finite \(\pi\)-groups (for a set \(\pi\) of primes), or the class of locally finite- soluble \(\pi\)-groups. The main result of this impressive paper is Theorem 1: There is a set \({\mathfrak A}\) of \(2^{\omega_ 1}\) non-isomorphic e.c. \({\mathfrak X}\)-groups of cardinality \(\omega_ 1\) with the following properties: (i) if U and V are distinct members of \({\mathfrak A}\) and A and B are uncountable subgroups of U and V respectively, then A and B are not isomorphic; (ii) if A is an uncountable subgroup of \(U\in {\mathfrak A}\), then A is not isomorphic to any of its proper subgroups; (iii) (\(\diamond)\) every \(U\in {\mathfrak A}\) is a complete group. Here, \(\diamond\) denotes that Jensen's set theoretic principle \(\diamond\), which cannot be proved from ZFC but is consistent with it, is used in the proof of property (iii) of the groups constructed. For universal locally finite groups, that is, the case when \({\mathfrak X}\) is the class of all locally finite groups, the corresponding result was proved by \textit{K. Hickin} [Trans. Am. Math. Soc. 239, 213-227 (1978; Zbl 0386.20014)], without using \(\diamond\). The present construction, which is very intricate, is an amalgam of Hickin's methods with model theoretic techniques. The paper is carefully written, and the relevant set theory and model theory is clearly described for the benefit of group theorists unaccustomed to this kind of thing. Now universal locally finite groups are well known to be simple. On the other hand, it is shown to follow from the classification of finite simple groups that if \({\mathfrak X}\) (as described in the first paragraph) is not the class of all locally finite groups, then an e.c. \({\mathfrak X}\)- group cannot be simple. In particular, for such \({\mathfrak X}\), the groups in the set \({\mathfrak A}\) are not simple. By (iii) they are not characteristically simple either, disproving a conjecture of Kegel that e.c. \({\mathfrak X}\)-groups are characteristically simple. Actually a more careful study of the construction shows that if \(U\in {\mathfrak A}\), then every non-trivial normal subgroup of U is uncountable. Thus, since it is also known that the set of normal subgroups is totally ordered by inclusion, distinct normal subgroups of U are non-isomorphic and hence one sees that U is not characteristically simple without using \(\diamond.\) It is interesting to note that while one obtains uncountable complete locally finite p-groups in this way, a very simple argument shows that a countable locally finite p-group cannot be complete. In fact no example appears to be known of a complete countably infinite locally finite group.
    0 references
    existentially closed groups
    0 references
    Jensen's principle
    0 references
    locally finite groups
    0 references
    universal locally finite groups
    0 references
    locally finite \(\pi \) -groups
    0 references
    locally finite-soluble \(\pi \) -groups
    0 references
    uncountable subgroups
    0 references
    characteristically simple
    0 references
    normal subgroups
    0 references
    complete locally finite p-groups
    0 references
    0 references

    Identifiers

    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references