Euclid's common notions and the theory of equivalence (Q2152377)

From MaRDI portal
Revision as of 23:05, 19 March 2024 by Openalex240319060354 (talk | contribs) (Set OpenAlex properties.)
scientific article
Language Label Description Also known as
English
Euclid's common notions and the theory of equivalence
scientific article

    Statements

    Euclid's common notions and the theory of equivalence (English)
    0 references
    0 references
    8 July 2022
    0 references
    This is a detailed, definitive study of the authenticity and function of the five common notions contained in Heiberg's standard edition of Euclid's \textit{Elements}. The common notions are: \(\bullet\) CN1: Things which are equal to the same thing are also equal to one another. \(\bullet\) CN2: If equals are added to equals, the wholes are equal. \(\bullet\) CN3: If equals are subtracted from equals, the remainders are equal. \(\bullet\) CN4: Things which coincide with one another are equal to one another. \(\bullet\) CN5: The whole is greater than the part. The authenticity analysis reveals that CN1--CN3 are authentic, given that they are also mentioned in Euclid's \textit{Data}, by Plato and Aristotle, and ``are at work in a great number of theorems.'' On the other hand there are a wide range of reasons to believe that CN4 and CN5 are inauthentic. These are: (i) ``The extant mathematical works by Archimedes, Geminus, Zenodorus, and, later on, Pappus mention neither CN4 nor CN5.'' (ii) ``The common notion on coincidence (CN4) appears to be employed only three times in the \textit{Elements}, namely, on the occasions on which Euclid resorts to the procedure of superposition: \textit{Elements} I, 4 and 8, and \textit{Elements} III, 24.'' (iii) ``Euclid never explicitly mentions [CN5] in the demonstrations.'' (iv) Proclus ``states that Heron, in his lost commentary on the \textit{Elements}, only accepted the first three common notions.'' These lead the author to ``advance the hypothesis that in Heron's times the \textit{Elements} only contained three common notions.'' \par Regarding their function, CN1--CN3 ``were first conceived in order to construct a geometrical theory of equivalence''; they ''provide a neat axiomatization of equality and additivity.'' \par CN4 and CN5 ``are used to compare to one another the squares (or parallelogrammic regions) that have been obtained through the process of equiampliability. This comparison is, in a sense, the goal of the theory of equivalence itself and in this respect CN4 and CN5 may be regarded as the crowning of the axiomatic system for such a theory. In another sense, however, CN4 and CN5 are external to the theory itself. They do not need to be embedded into a deductive chain of propositions (such as \textit{Elements} I, 35--45); rather, they are directly employed in order to compare figures: there is nothing to prove by them \(\ldots\) The comparison of figures through CN4 and CN5 occurs by means of \textit{diagrammatic inferences}, whereas CN1--CN3 are purely propositional principles.''
    0 references
    foundations of geometry
    0 references
    history of geometry
    0 references
    theory of equivalence
    0 references
    axiomatics
    0 references

    Identifiers