Proof theory of paraconsistent quantum logic (Q1749807)

From MaRDI portal
scientific article
Language Label Description Also known as
English
Proof theory of paraconsistent quantum logic
scientific article

    Statements

    Proof theory of paraconsistent quantum logic (English)
    0 references
    0 references
    28 May 2018
    0 references
    Minimal quantum logic or orthologic was introduced in [\textit{G. Birkhoff} and \textit{J. von Neumann}, Ann. Math. (2) 37, 823--843 (1936; JFM 62.1061.04); \textit{G. Birkhoff} and \textit{J. von Neumann}, Ann. Math. (2) 37, 823--843 (1936; Zbl 0015.14603)], and its Kripke-style semantics was provided in [\textit{R. I. Goldblatt}, J. Philos. Log. 3, 19--35 (1974; Zbl 0278.02023)]. Its Gentzen-type sequent calculi have been studied in [\textit{N. J. Cutland} and \textit{P. F. Gibbins}, Log. Anal., Nouv. Sér. 25, 221--248 (1982; Zbl 0518.03029); \textit{C. Faggian} and \textit{G. Sambin}, Int. J. Theor. Phys. 37, No. 1, 31--37 (1998; Zbl 0904.03031); the reviewer, in: Handbook of quantum logic and quantum structures. Quantum logic. With a foreword by Anatolij Dvurečenskij. Amsterdam: Elsevier/North-Holland. 227--260 (2009; Zbl 1273.03089); the reviewer, Int. J. Theor. Phys. 33, No. 7, 1427--1443 (1994; Zbl 0809.03045); the reviewer, Int. J. Theor. Phys. 33, No. 1, 103--113 (1994; Zbl 0798.03062); the reviewer, J. Symb. Log. 45, 339--352 (1980; Zbl 0437.03034); \textit{S. Tamura}, Kobe J. Math. 5, No. 1, 133--150 (1988; Zbl 0663.03050); \textit{M. Takano}, Int. J. Theor. Phys. 34, No. 4, 649--654 (1995; Zbl 0824.03032)]. Belnap and Dunn's paraconsistent four-valued logic [\textit{J. M. Dunn}, Philos. Stud. 29, No. 3, 149--168 (1976; Zbl 1435.03043); \textit{N. D. Belnap jun.}, in: Mod. uses of multiple-valued logic, 5th int. Symp., Bloomington 1975, 5--37 (1977; Zbl 0417.03009); \textit{N. D. Belnap jun.}, in: Mod. Uses of multiple-valued Logic, 5th int. Symp., Bloomington 1975, 5--37 (1977; Zbl 0424.03012)], a.k.a. \textit{A. R. Anderson} and \textit{N. D. Belnap jun.}'s first-degree entailment [Entailment. The logic of relevance and necessity. Vol. I. Princeton, N. J.: Princeton University Press (1975; Zbl 0323.02030); \textit{A. R. Anderson} et al., Entailment. The logic of relevance and necessity. Vol. II. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press (1992; Zbl 0921.03025)], is known to be equivalent to the $\{\wedge,\vee,\sim\}$-fragment of Nelson's paraconsistent four-valued logic [\textit{D. Nelson}, J. Symb. Log. 14, 16--26 (1949; Zbl 0033.24304); \textit{A. Almukdad} and \textit{D. Nelson}, J. Symb. Log. 49, 231--233 (1984; Zbl 0575.03016)]. Its Gentzen-type sequent calculi have been investigated in [\textit{J. M. Font}, Log. J. IGPL 5, No. 3, 413--440 (1997; Zbl 0871.03012); \textit{J. M. Font}, Log. J. IGPL 7, No. 5, 671--672 (1999; Zbl 0937.03028); \textit{N. Kamide} and \textit{H. Wansing}, Proof theory of N4-paraconsistent logics. London: College Publications (2015; Zbl 1436.03003); \textit{A. P. Pynko}, Math. Log. Q. 41, No. 4, 442--454 (1995; Zbl 0837.03019); Zbl 0323.02030]. Paraconsistent quantum logic, a hybrid of minimal quantum logic and paraconsistent four-valued logic, was introduced in [\textit{M. L. Dalla Chiara} and \textit{R. Giuntini}, Synthese 125, No. 1--2, 55--68 (2000; Zbl 0969.03070)]. A cut-free Gentzen-type sequent calculus for it was investigated in [Zbl 0904.03031] by extending the $\{\wedge,\vee\}$-fragment of basic logic in [\textit{G. Sambin} et al., J. Symb. Log. 65, No. 3, 979--1013 (2000; Zbl 0969.03017)]. This paper introduces four cut-free Gentzen-type sequent calculi for paraconsistent quantum logic. The first is obtained by Takano [loc. cit.] by deleting some initial sequents and negated logical inference rules. The second comes from a Gentzen-type sequent calculus for the $\{\wedge,\vee\}$-fragment of basic logic by adding some negated logical inference rules. The third derives from a Gentzen-type sequent calculus for the $\{\wedge,\vee\}$-fragment of \textit{H. Aoyama}'s weak sequent calculus LB [``On a weak system of sequent calculus'', J. Log. Philos. 3, 29--37 (2003)] by adding some negated logical inference rules. The fourth, PQL, is obtained from the third by restricting the sequent definition, being obtainable from a Gentzen-type sequent calculus for \textit{lattice logic} [\textit{G. Restall} and \textit{F. Paoli}, J. Symb. Log. 70, No. 4, 1108--1126 (2005; Zbl 1100.03049); \textit{J. Schulte Moenting}, Algebra Univers. 12, 290--321 (1981; Zbl 0528.03029)] or from \textit{finite sum-product logic} [\textit{J. R. B. Cockett} and \textit{R. A. G. Seely}, Theory Appl. Categ. 8, 63--99 (2001; Zbl 0969.03071)] by adding some negated logical inference rules. These four calculi are logically equivalent. A first-order predicate extension FPQL of PQL is shown to be decidable after the decidability of first-order \textit{substructural logics} without contraction rules.
    0 references
    paraconsistent logic
    0 references
    quantum logic
    0 references
    sequent calculus
    0 references
    cut-elimination theorem
    0 references

    Identifiers

    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references