Stationary logic and its friends. II (Q1820150)

From MaRDI portal
scientific article
Language Label Description Also known as
English
Stationary logic and its friends. II
scientific article

    Statements

    Stationary logic and its friends. II (English)
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    1986
    0 references
    This paper is the successor to Part I [reviewed above; see Zbl 0614.03032]. The three sections of the paper can be read independently. The first two sections assume some familiarity with stationary logic, denoted L(aa). The third section concerns a closure operation for abstract logic. In the first section we define, for regular \(\lambda\), the \(\lambda\)- interpretation of L(aa), denoted \(L(aa^{\lambda})\). In this notation, the standard interpretation is \(L(aa^{\omega})\). The most easily understandable case occurs when \(\lambda^{<\lambda}=\lambda\). Then for models with universe \(\lambda^+\), \(aa^{\lambda}\) expresses ''for all but a nonstationary set of ordinals of cofinality \(\lambda\) ''. We show if \(\lambda^{<\lambda}=\lambda\), then \(L(aa^{\lambda})\) has the same validities as \(L(aa^{\omega})\) and \(L(aa^{\lambda})\) is (\(\lambda\),\(\omega)\)-compact. The second section is devoted to the proof of the consistency of the following approximation to the \(\Delta\)-closure of L(Q) being contained in L(aa). Suppose \(L_ 1\cap L_ 2=L_ 0\), \(\psi_ 1\in L_ 1(Q)\) and \(\psi_ 2\in L_ 2(Q)\). Further suppose every finitely determinate \(L_ 0\)-structure either can be expanded to a model of exactly one of \(\psi_ 1\) of \(\psi_ 2\) or can be expanded to a finitely determinate model of exactly one of \(\psi_ 1\) or \(\psi_ 2\). Then there is a sentence \(\theta \in L_ 0(aa)\) such that every finitely determinate model of \(\psi_ 1\) satisfies \(\theta\) and no finitely determinate model of \(\psi_ 2\) satisfies \(\theta\). (So \(\theta\) separates the reducts of finitely determinate models of \(\psi_ 1\) from those of \(\psi_ 2.)\) The third section is a prolonged observation motivated by the algebraic intuition that homomorphic images are as fundamental as subalgebras. A common requirement on a logic is that one can talk about definable substructures. However, many common logics, such as L(Q), do not allow us to talk about definable homomorphic images; i.e., modeling out by definable congruences. We show that demanding a logic be congruence closed is innocuous. Every logic has an easily described congruence closure with inherits most of the good properties of the logic.
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    L(aa)
    0 references
    closure operation for abstract logic
    0 references
    \(\lambda \)-interpretation
    0 references
    consistency
    0 references
    finitely determinate model
    0 references
    definable substructures
    0 references
    definable congruences
    0 references
    congruence closure
    0 references
    0 references