Generic absoluteness and the continuum (Q1864712)

From MaRDI portal
scientific article
Language Label Description Also known as
English
Generic absoluteness and the continuum
scientific article

    Statements

    Generic absoluteness and the continuum (English)
    0 references
    15 May 2003
    0 references
    Generic absoluteness for a class of forcings states that \((H(\aleph_2),\in)\prec_1 (V^B,\in)\) whenever \(V^B\) is a Boolean-valued extension of the universe by a complete Boolean algebra from that class. The main result of the paper is that generic absoluteness for Boolean-valued extensions that preserve stationary subsets of \(\omega_1\) implies the continuum has a well-order of length \(\omega_2\) (definable in \(H(\aleph_2)\) from a single \(\omega_1\)-sequence of reals). Given the one-to-one sequence \(\langle r_\alpha:\alpha\in\omega_1\rangle\) of elements of the Cantor set the coding of subsets of \(\omega\) by ordinals in \(\omega_2\) proceeds as follows. To every countable set of ordinals \(X\) one associates the real \(r_X=r_{\text{otp} X}\). Furthermore the first-difference function \(\Delta(x,y)=\min\{n:x(n)\neq y(n)\}\) on the Cantor set is employed to associate (potentially) to every subset \(S\) of \(\omega_1\) three ordinals \(\gamma>\beta>\alpha\geq\omega_1\) where \(\gamma\) is written as the increasing union of a continuous and increasing sequence \(\langle N_\nu:\nu\in\omega_1\rangle\) of countable sets, all such that \(N_\nu\cap\omega_1\in S\) if and only if \(\Delta(r_{N_\nu\cap\alpha},r_{N_\nu\cap\beta})\) is the largest of the values \(\Delta(u,v)\), where \(u\) and \(v\) can be \(r_{N_\nu\cap\alpha}\), \(r_{N_\nu\cap\beta}\) and \(r_{N_\nu}\), respectively. Now if \((\gamma,\beta,\alpha)\) were associated to two sets \(S\) and \(T\) in this way, with sequences \(\langle N_\nu\rangle_\nu\) and \(\langle M_\nu\rangle_\nu\) respectively, then, since \(N_\nu=M_\nu\) for a cub set of \(\nu\), one would find that \(S\) and \(T\) were equal modulo the cub filter. As one can find \(2^{\aleph_1}\) inequivalent sets, the possibility of assigning a triple and sequence to every subset of \(\omega_1\), abbreviated \(\theta_{\text{AC}}\) in the paper, would imply \(2^{\aleph_1}=\aleph_2\). It turns that one can find for each \(S\) a generic extension in which stationary subsets of \(\omega_1\) are preserved and in which a triple and sequence can be found -- generic absoluteness yields the existence of these objects in the real world and thus the equality \(2^{\aleph_1}=\aleph_2\). Furthermore, the principle \(\theta_{\text{AC}}\) violates the weak diamond of \textit{K. J. Devlin} and \textit{S. Shelah} [Isr. J. Math. 29, 239-247 (1978; Zbl 0403.03040)], hence it implies \(2^{\aleph_0}=2^{\aleph_1}\). A careful inspection of the proof will show how to define a well-order of \(\mathbb R\) in \(H(\aleph_2)\). It seems unknown whether the parameter \(\langle r_\alpha:\alpha\in\omega_1\rangle\) can be replaced by something more effective, e.g., a countable sequence of ordinals -- as one can construct a nonmeasurable set of reals from an \(\omega_1\)-sequence of reals [\textit{S. Shelah}, Isr. J. Math. 48, 1-47 (1984; Zbl 0596.03055)], one could go so far as to argue that the ``more'' above is a bit misplaced.
    0 references
    generic absoluteness
    0 references
    \(H(\aleph_2)\)
    0 references
    Continuum Hypothesis
    0 references
    Boolean-valued extensions
    0 references
    0 references

    Identifiers