Dependent \(T\) and existence of limit models (Q482659)

From MaRDI portal
scientific article
Language Label Description Also known as
English
Dependent \(T\) and existence of limit models
scientific article

    Statements

    Dependent \(T\) and existence of limit models (English)
    0 references
    0 references
    6 January 2015
    0 references
    It is well-known that saturated models of a complete first-order theory are unique up to isomorphism given their cardinality. The author generalized this to abstract elementary classes, considering the so-called \((\lambda,\kappa)\) limit models for pairs of cardinals \(\kappa<\lambda\). In this paper, he studies the question when such models exist in a complete first-order theory. Recall that a universal model \(M\models T\) of cardinality \(\lambda\) is a \textit{\((\lambda,\kappa)\) superlimit} model if for all ordinals \(\delta<\lambda^+\) of cofinality \(\kappa\) and for all \(\prec\)-continuous increasing sequences \((M_i:i\leq\delta)\) with \(M_i\cong M\) for all \(i<\delta\), one has \(M_\delta\cong M\). More generally, if there is a function \(F\) from the collection of models of \(T\) of cardinality \(\lambda\) to itself satisfying \(N\prec F(N)\) for all \(N\), such that {\parindent=6mm \begin{itemize} \item[(a)] for all ordinals \(\delta<\lambda^+\) of cofinality \(\kappa\) and all \(\prec\)-continuous increasing sequences \((M_i:i\leq\delta)\) with \(F(M_{i+1})\prec M_{i+2}\) for all \(i<\delta\) one has \(M\cong\bigcup_{i<\delta}M_i\), then \(M\) is a \textit{\((\lambda,\kappa)\) strong limit}; \item [(b)] for all \(\prec\)-continuous increasing sequences \((M_i:i<\lambda^+)\) with \(F(M_{i+1})\prec M_{i+2}\) for all \(i<\lambda^+\) there is a closed unbounded subset \(C\subseteq\lambda^+\) such that \(M\cong M_\delta\) for all \(\delta\in C\) of cofinality \(\kappa\), then \(M\) is a \textit{\((\lambda,\kappa)\) normal limit}. \end{itemize}} If \(F\) takes \(\prec\)-increasing continuous sequences as argument, and we replace the condition \(M_{i+1}\prec F(M_{i+1})\prec M_{i+2}\) by \(M_{i+1}\prec F(M_j:j\leq i+1)\prec M_{i+2}\), we obtain the notion of \textit{\((\lambda,\kappa)\) medium limit} from (a) and \textit{\((\lambda,\kappa)\) weak limit} from (b). If we replace \(M_{i+1}\prec F(M_{i+1})\prec M_{i+2}\) by \(M_{i+1}\prec N\prec M_{i+2}\) for some \(N\equiv_{M_{i+1}}F(M_{i+1})\) (and similarly for sequences), we obtain the notions of \textit{\((\lambda,\kappa)\) invariantly strong/normal/medium/weak limit}. Clearly, superlimit implies strong limit, which implies both medium and normal limit, either of which implies weak limit. There are also variants \textit{limit\(^+\)}, \textit{limit\(^-\)}, and for replacing the set of ordinals of cofinality \(\kappa\) by some arbitrary stationary subset of \(\lambda^+\), but this would go beyond the limits of this review. The author shows that {\parindent=6mm \begin{itemize} \item[(1)] The theory of dense linear orders has \((\lambda,\kappa)\) invariantly medium limits, but no \((\lambda,\kappa)\) superlimit. \item [(2)] Strongly independent theories have no \((\lambda,\kappa)\) invariantly medium limit; independent theories have no \((\lambda,\kappa)\) medium limit. \end{itemize}} He conjectures that dependent theories have \((\lambda,\kappa)\) invariantly medium limits.
    0 references
    limit model
    0 references
    dense linear order
    0 references
    strong dependence
    0 references
    dependence
    0 references

    Identifiers

    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references