Why make things simple when you can make them complicated? An appreciation of Lewis Carroll's symbolic logic (Q2239387)

From MaRDI portal
scientific article
Language Label Description Also known as
English
Why make things simple when you can make them complicated? An appreciation of Lewis Carroll's symbolic logic
scientific article

    Statements

    Why make things simple when you can make them complicated? An appreciation of Lewis Carroll's symbolic logic (English)
    0 references
    0 references
    3 November 2021
    0 references
    The mathematician Charles Lutwidge Dodgson (1832--1898) wrote under his pen name Lewis Carroll not only children's books [Alice's adventures in Wonderland. 150th anniversary edition. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press (2015; Zbl 1359.01094)] but also logic books, e.g. [The game of logic. (German) Stuttgart-Bad Canstatt: Frommann-Holzboog (1998; Zbl 0915.00004)]. As a logician, Carroll can be perceived as both an innovator (symbolic notations, logic diagrams, logic trees) and a conservative who defended the traditional doctrine of existential import. The latter goes back to Aristotle and is the idea that universally quantified statements (e.g., ``I aced all my exams'') should not be vacuously true (because I didn't take any). The author's goal is ``to untangle this dilemma by exploring Carroll's guidelines in the design of his logic'' (p.~359), and the conclusion he reaches is that Carroll ``favoured the practical convenience of the theory over the ease of the logician. The reason is that Carroll believed in the social utility of logic'' (p.~372). The article is divided into seven sections: 1.~Introduction (ca.\,1 p.) -- 2.~The problem of eimination (ca.\,3 pp.) -- 3.~An overview of Carroll's logic (ca.\,3 pp.) -- 4.~Carroll's contributions to logic (ca.ł,3 pp.) -- 5.~The theory of existential import (ca.\,3 pp.) -- 6.~The utility of symbolic logic (ca.\,3.5 pp.) -- 7.~Conclusion (ca.\,0.5 p.) -- followed by a bibliography (ca.\,4 pp.). \par The paper is written by someone who has written extensively on Carroll -- it thus doubles as a review of the recent literature on Carroll -- and reads well. Those interested in seeing the dilemma resolved in Sections 5 and 6 will, however, arrive at their destination via many detours that paint a picture broader than strictly necessary for the task at hand (which is probably due to the fact that the article under review is based on a talk the author gave in 2017). As far as the crux of the matter is concerned (i.\,e., Sections 5 and 6), the reviewer would rate an earlier paper by the author higher [``On the social utility of symbolic logic: Lewis Carroll against the logicians'', Stud. Metodol. 35, 133--150 (2015; \url{doi:10.14746/sm.2015.35.10})]. \par The few typos do not obfuscate the intended meaning. Confusing, though, is the author's idiosyncratic capitalization (e.g., `proposition' and `conclusion' are always capitalized, but `argument' never).
    0 references
    0 references
    Lewis Carroll
    0 references
    Dodgson
    0 references
    history of logic
    0 references
    logic in 19th century England
    0 references
    symbolic logic
    0 references
    existential import
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references

    Identifiers