Relative contingency and bimodality (Q1945710): Difference between revisions

From MaRDI portal
Added link to MaRDI item.
ReferenceBot (talk | contribs)
Changed an Item
 
(4 intermediate revisions by 3 users not shown)
Property / author
 
Property / author: Claudio E. A. Pizzi / rank
Normal rank
 
Property / author
 
Property / author: Claudio E. A. Pizzi / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / MaRDI profile type
 
Property / MaRDI profile type: MaRDI publication profile / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / full work available at URL
 
Property / full work available at URL: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11787-012-0071-8 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / OpenAlex ID
 
Property / OpenAlex ID: W1969401102 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q3787968 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Necessity and contingency / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q3026978 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q3669374 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: The logic of non-contingency / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: The modal logic of agreement and noncontingency / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Minimal non-contingency logic / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Necessity and relative contingency / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Relative necessity / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Completeness and definability in the logic of noncontingency / rank
 
Normal rank

Latest revision as of 07:59, 6 July 2024

scientific article
Language Label Description Also known as
English
Relative contingency and bimodality
scientific article

    Statements

    Relative contingency and bimodality (English)
    0 references
    8 April 2013
    0 references
    The paper studies the logics with a deontic operator \(O\) which is defined as \(OA =_{\mathrm{def}} \square(Q \supset A)\), where \(\square\) is logical necessity and \(Q\) is a propositional constant, axiomatized by \(\lozenge Q\) with the intuitive meaning ``the moral (legal) code is applied''. The minimal contingency system \(K\Delta\tau w\) is an extension of classical (propositional) logic in the signature \(\bot,\supset\) by endowing it with a new connective \(\Delta\), where \(\Delta\) may be read as ``non-contingently'' or ``absolutely'', and with a new constant \(\tau\), which is intended to have the meaning of some statement which is essentially contingent. The additional axioms are: \(K\Delta\)1. \(\Delta p \equiv \Delta\neg p\); \(K\Delta\)2. \((\Delta p \land \Delta q) \supset \Delta(p \land q)\); \(K\Delta\)3. \((\Delta p \land \nabla(\neg p \lor r)) \supset \Delta(p \lor q)\), where \(\nabla A =_{\mathrm{def}} \neg \Delta A\); \(\Delta\tau w\). \(\Delta \tau \supset \Delta p\). The additional inference rules are \({\vdash A} \longrightarrow {\vdash \Delta A}\) and \({\vdash A \equiv B} \longrightarrow {\vdash \Delta A \equiv \Delta B}\). In Section 2, an adequate semantics for the system \(K\Delta\tau w\) is constructed. Necessity can be defined as \(\square A =_{\mathrm{def}} \Delta A \land \Delta(\tau \supset A)\) and the definitional equivalence of the systems \(K\Delta\tau w\) and \(K\square\tau w\) is proven in Section 3. In Section 4, the following bimodal system \(K\square O\) is introduced and studied: \(K\). \(\square(p \supset q) \supset (\square p \supset \square q)\); \(O\). \(O(p \supset q) \supset (O p \supset O q)\); \(\square O\). \(\square p \supset O p\); and the inference rules are modus ponens, substitution, necessitation and replacement of proved material equivalents.
    0 references
    0 references
    contingency
    0 references
    necessity
    0 references
    propositional constant
    0 references
    bimodal logics
    0 references

    Identifiers