The dynamic evolution of preferences (Q2373374): Difference between revisions

From MaRDI portal
RedirectionBot (talk | contribs)
Removed claim: author (P16): Item:Q1331853
Import241208061232 (talk | contribs)
Normalize DOI.
 
(4 intermediate revisions by 4 users not shown)
Property / DOI
 
Property / DOI: 10.1007/s00199-006-0121-7 / rank
Normal rank
 
Property / author
 
Property / author: Yossef Spiegel / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / MaRDI profile type
 
Property / MaRDI profile type: MaRDI publication profile / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / full work available at URL
 
Property / full work available at URL: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-006-0121-7 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / OpenAlex ID
 
Property / OpenAlex ID: W2118614669 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q4783379 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q4805737 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Walrasian equilibrium with gross substitutes / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Evolution of Preferences1 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Nash equilibrium and the evolution of preferences / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q4223194 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: The evolutionary role of toughness in bargaining / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Market design with endogenous preferences / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: What to maximize if you must / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: The indirect evolutionary approach to explaining fair allocations / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Evolution of interdependent preferences in aggregative games / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: The strategic advantage of negatively interdependent preferences. / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Continuous Auctions and Insider Trading / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Monotone Comparative Statics / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Dominance solvability and Cournot stability / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Evolutionary dynamics on infinite strategy spaces / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: On the evolution of individualistic preferences: An incomplete information scenario / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: A biological basis for expected and non-expected utility / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: The evolution of attitudes to risk: Lottery tickets and relative wealth / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Existence and Uniqueness of Equilibrium Points for Concave N-Person Games / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Evolutionary stability in asymmetric games / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Evolutionarily stable strategies and game dynamics / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: The Evolution of Walrasian Behavior / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / cites work
 
Property / cites work: Q4885257 / rank
 
Normal rank
Property / DOI
 
Property / DOI: 10.1007/S00199-006-0121-7 / rank
 
Normal rank

Latest revision as of 06:22, 18 December 2024

scientific article
Language Label Description Also known as
English
The dynamic evolution of preferences
scientific article

    Statements

    The dynamic evolution of preferences (English)
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    0 references
    19 July 2007
    0 references
    The paper characterizes dynamic evolution of preferences in a class of strategic interactions providing simple conditions characterizing the limiting distribution of preferences and apply their results to study the evolutionary emergence of overconfidence and interdependent preferences. Consider a class of strategic interactions in which two players \(i\) and \(j\) with identical strategy sets as a subset of the reals engage in a symmetric game whose payoffs are given by the same underlying payoff function \(\Pi :\mathbb{R}^2\to \mathbb{R},\) i.e., \(\Pi ^i( x^i,x^j) =\Pi ( x^i,x^j) \) and \(\Pi ^j( x^i,x^j) =\Pi ( x^j,x^i) \) where \(x^i,x^j\) is a typical strategy pair and \(\Pi ^i( x^i,x^j) ,\Pi ^j( x^i,x^j) \) denote the respective payoffs. \ Let \(\tau ^i,\tau ^j\) denote player types drawn from a compact sub-interval \(T\) of the reals and a function \(B:R^{3}\to R\) provide the (symmetric) dispositions of the two players, \(B^i( x^i,x^j,\tau ^i) =B( x^i,x^j,\tau ^i) \) and \(B^j( x^i,x^j,\tau ^j) =B( x^j,x^i,\tau ^j) ,\) which differentiate their perceived payoffs \(U^i()\) and \(U^j()\) from their realized or true payoffs \(\Pi ^i\) and \(\Pi ^j\), i.e., \(U^i( x^i,x^j,\tau ^i) =\Pi ^i( x^i,x^j) +B^i( x^i,x^j,\tau ^i) \) and \(U^j( x^i,x^j,\tau ^j) =\Pi ^j( x^i,x^j) +B^j( x^i,x^j,\tau ^j) .\) Let \(\Gamma \) denote the game in which the players \(i\) and \(j\) choose strategies \(x^i,x^j\) to maximize their perceived payoffs \(U^i(.,\tau ^i)\),\(U^j(.,\tau ^j)\) and obtain true payoffs \(\Pi ^i\) and \(\Pi ^j. \) Assumption A. \(\Gamma \) has a unique pure strategy Nash equilibrium \(\widehat{x}^i( \tau ^i,\tau ^j) , \widehat{x}^j( \tau ^i,\tau ^j) \) for each pair of player types \(( \tau ^i,\tau ^j) \in T\times T.\) Under this assumption, the true payoffs in the equilibrium are given by the following fitness functions: \(f^i( \tau ^i,\tau ^j) =\Pi ^i( \widehat{x}^i( \tau ^i,\tau ^j) ,\widehat{x} ^j( \tau ^i,\tau ^j) ) \) and \(f^j( \tau ^i,\tau ^j) =\Pi ^j( \widehat{x}^i( \tau ^i,\tau ^j) ,\widehat{x}^j( \tau ^i,\tau ^j) ) .\) To study the evolution of disposition the authors adopt an indirect evolutionary approach by considering a ``types game'' in which each player chooses a type \(\tau ^i,\tau ^j\) in \(T\) and receives payoffs according to the fitness functions. Assumption B. The types game is dominance solvable. They consider a continuous time model in which at each point of time \(t\geq 0,\) the population of individual types is characterized by the distribution \(G_{t}\in \Delta ( T) \), where \( \Delta ( T) .\) They assume that the initial distribution \(G_{0}\) has full support over \(T\). At each \(t\), individuals are randomly matched in pairs to play the game \(\Gamma \). \ Dropping the superscripts \(i\) and \(j\) due to the symmetry of the problem, the average fitness levels of individuals of type \(\tau \) at time \(t\) is given by \(\int f( \tau ,\tau ^{\prime }) dG_{t}( \tau ^{\prime }) .\) \ They assume that the distribution of types evolves according to the differential equation: \[ \frac{d}{dt}G_{t}( S) =\int_{S}g( \tau ,G_{t}) dG_{t}( \tau ) ,S\subset T\text{ Borel measurable} \] where \(g:T\times \Delta ( T) \to R\) is a continuous growth-rate function satisfying: \[ g( \tau ,G_{t}) >g( \widetilde{\tau },G_{t}) \Longleftrightarrow \int f( \tau ,\tau ^{\prime }) dG_{t}( \tau ^{\prime }) >\int f( \widetilde{\tau },\tau ^{\prime }) dG_{t}( \tau ^{\prime }) \] and the normalization, to ensure that \(G_{t}\) remains a distribution function, \(\int_{S}g( \tau ,G_{t}) dG_{t}( \tau ) =0\) for each \(t.\) \ The evolutionary dynamical system reflects the idea that the proportion of more successful types increases at the expense of the less successful types perhaps because they have more descendants or because they are imitated more often. The formulation is also compatible with the assumption that successful types translate into stronger influence rather than numerical proliferation. Under certain regularity conditions the dynamical system has a well-defined solution. The main theorem shows that any serially dominated strategy must eventually become extinct under any payoff-monotonic population dynamics and, in particular, in a dominance solvable game any such dynamics must converge in distribution to a point mass at the unique action surviving the iterated elimination of strictly dominated strategies. By this theorem, the support of any limiting distribution must be a subset of the set \(U\) of serially undominated strategies. \ In games where the set \(U\) can be characterized or computed easily, the theorem gives useful predictions regarding the dynamic evolutionary outcomes. \ Two such special cases, game which are dominance solvable and the case of strategic complementarities, are dealt with in two further theorems. \ The authors go on to consider two applications of their main result, interpreting the dispositions as perception biases representing over and under-confidence, optimism or pessimism and considering interdependent preferences in which players can give different weights to their opponents' payoffs in their utility functions allowing for envy or altruism.
    0 references
    evolutionary dynamical games
    0 references
    limiting distributions
    0 references
    stability of evolutionary process
    0 references
    overconfidence
    0 references
    interdependent preferences
    0 references

    Identifiers